E Pluribus Unum?
The Fight Over Identity Politics
Identity Politics Strengthens Democracy
Stacey Y. Abrams
Recent political upheavals
have reinvigorated a long-running debate about the role of identity in American
politics—and especially American elections. Electoral politics have long been a
lagging indicator of social change. For hundreds of years, the electorate was
limited by laws that explicitly deprived women, African Americans, and other
groups of the right to vote. (Efforts to deny voting rights and suppress voter turnout continue today, in less overt forms but with the same ill
intent.) When marginalized groups finally gained access to the ballot, it took
time for them to organize around opposition to the specific forms of
discrimination and mistreatment that continued to plague them—and longer still
for political parties and candidates to respond to such activism. In recent
decades, however, rapid demographic and technological changes have accelerated
this process, bolstering demands for inclusion and raising expectations in
communities that had long been conditioned to accept a slow pace of change. In
the past decade, the U.S. electorate has become younger and more ethnically
diverse. Meanwhile, social media has changed the political landscape. Facebook
captures examples of inequality and makes them available for endless replay.
Twitter links the voiceless to newsmakers. Instagram immortalizes the faces and
consequences of discrimination. Isolated cruelties are yoked into a powerful
narrative of marginalization that spurs a common cause.
These changes have encouraged
activists and political challengers to make demands with a high level of
specificity—to take the identities that dominant groups have used to oppress
them and convert them into tools of democratic justice. Critics of this
phenomenon, including Francis Fukuyama (“Against Identity Politics,” September/October 2018), condemn it as the practice of
“identity politics.” But Fukuyama’s criticism relies on a number of
misjudgments. First, Fukuyama complains that “again and again, groups have come
to believe that their identities—whether national, religious, ethnic, sexual,
gender, or otherwise—are not receiving adequate recognition.” In the United
States, marginalized groups have indeed come to believe this—because it is
true. Fukuyama also warns that Americans are fragmenting “into segments based
on ever-narrower identities, threatening the possibility of deliberation and
collective action by society as a whole.” But what Fukuyama laments as
“fracturing” is in reality the result of marginalized groups finally overcoming
centuries-long efforts to erase them from the American polity—activism that
will strengthen democratic rule, not threaten it.
THE CLASS TRAP
Fukuyama claims that the Democratic Party “has a major choice to make.” The party, he writes, can
continue “doubling down on the mobilization of the identity groups that today
supply its most fervent activists: African Americans, Hispanics, professional
women, the LGBT community, and so on.” Or it can take Fukuyama’s preferred
tack, focusing more on economic issues in an attempt to “win back some of the
white working-class voters . . . who have defected to the Republican Party in
recent elections.”
Fukuyama
and other critics of identity politics contend that broad categories such as
economic class contain multitudes and that all attention should focus on wide
constructs rather than the substrates of inequality. But such arguments fail to
acknowledge that some members of any particular economic class have advantages
not enjoyed by others in their cohort. U.S. history abounds with examples of
members of dominant groups abandoning class solidarity after concluding that
opportunity is a zero-sum game. The oppressed have often aimed their impotent
rage at those too low on the social scale to even attempt rebellion. This is
particularly true in the catchall category known as “the working class.”
Conflict between black and white laborers stretches back to the earliest eras
in U.S. history, which witnessed tensions between African slaves and European
indentured servants. Racism and sexism have long tarnished the heroic story of
the U.S. labor movement—defects that contributed to the rise of a segregated
middle class and to persistent pay disparities between men and women,
disparities exacerbated by racial differences. Indeed, the American working
class has consistently relied on people of color and women to push for improved
status for workers but has been slow to include them in the movement’s
victories.
The facile advice to focus
solely on class ignores these complex links among American notions of race,
gender, and economics. As Fukuyama himself notes, it has been difficult “to
create broad coalitions to fight for redistribution,” since “members of the
working class who also belong to higher-status identity groups (such as whites
in the United States) tend to resist making common cause with those below them,
and vice versa.” Fukuyama’s preferred strategy is also called into question by
the success that the Democratic Party enjoyed in 2018 by engaging in what he
derides as identity politics. Last year, I was the Democratic Party’s
gubernatorial nominee in Georgia and became the first African American woman in U.S. history to be nominated for governor
by a major political party. In my bid for office, I intentionally and
vigorously highlighted communities of color and other marginalized groups, not
to the exclusion of others but as a recognition of their specific policy needs.
My campaign championed reforms to eliminate police shootings of African
Americans, protect the LGBTQ community against ersatz religious freedom
legislation, expand Medicaid to save rural hospitals, and reaffirm that
undocumented immigrants deserve legal protections. I refused to accept the
notion that the voters most affected by these policies would invariably support
me simply because I was a member of a minority group. (The truth is that when
people do not hear their causes authentically addressed by campaigns, they
generally just don’t vote at all.) My campaign built an unprecedented coalition
of people of color, rural whites, suburban dwellers, and young people in the
Deep South by articulating an understanding of each group’s unique concerns
instead of trying to create a false image of universality. As a result, in a
midterm contest with a record-high turnout of nearly four million voters, I
received more votes than any Democrat in Georgia’s history, falling a scant
54,000 votes shy of victory in a contest riddled with voting irregularities that benefited my opponent.
DIFFERENT STROKES
Beyond electoral politics,
Fukuyama and others argue that by calling out ethnic, cultural, gender, or
sexual differences, marginalized groups harm themselves and their causes. By
enumerating and celebrating distinctions, the argument goes, they give their
opponents reasons for further excluding them. But minorities and the
marginalized have little choice but to fight against the particular methods of
discrimination employed against them. The marginalized did not create identity
politics: their identities have been forced on them by dominant groups, and
politics is the most effective method of revolt.
The marginalized did not
create identity politics: their identities have been forced on them by dominant
groups, and politics is the most effective method of revolt.
To seek redress and
inclusion, the first step is to identify the barriers to entry: an array of
laws and informal rules to proscribe, diminish, and isolate the marginalized.
The specific methods by which the United States has excluded women, Native
Americans, African Americans, immigrants, and the LGBTQ community from property
ownership, educational achievement, and political enfranchisement have
differed; so, too, have the most successful methods of fighting for
inclusion—hence the need for a politics that respects and reflects the
complicated nature of these identities and the ways in which they intersect.
The basis for sustainable progress is legal protections grounded in an
awareness of how identity has been used to deny opportunity. The LGBTQ
community is not included in civil rights protections, which means members may
lose their jobs or their right to housing or adoption. Antiabortion rules
disproportionately harm women of color and low-income women of every ethnicity,
affecting their economic capacity and threatening their very lives. Voter
suppression, the most insidious tool to thwart the effectiveness of identity
politics, demands the renewal of the Voting Rights Act of 1965 and massive
reforms at the state and local levels.
When the groups most affected
by these issues insist on acknowledgment of their intrinsic difference, it
should not be viewed as divisive. Embracing the distinct histories and
identities of groups in a democracy enhances the complexity and capacity of the
whole. For example, by claiming the unique attributes of womanhood—and, for
women of color, the experience of inhabiting the intersection of marginalized
gender and race—feminists have demonstrated how those characteristics could be
leveraged to enhance the whole. Take, for example, the Family and Medical Leave
Act, which feminists originally pushed for in order to guarantee women’s right
to give birth and still keep their jobs, but which men have also come to rely
on to take time off from work to care for children or aging parents.
The current demographic and
social evolution toward diversity in the United States has played out alongside
a trend toward greater economic and social inequality. These parallel but
distinct developments are inextricably bound together. The entrance of the
marginalized into the workplace, the commons, and the body politic—achieved
through litigation and legislation—spawned reactionary limits on their legal
standing and restrictions meant to block their complaints and prevent remedies.
The natural antidote to this condition is not a retrenchment to amorphous,
universal descriptors devoid of context or nuance. Instead, Americans must
thoughtfully pursue an expanded, identity-conscious politics. New, vibrant,
noisy voices represent the strongest tool to manage the growing pains of
multicultural coexistence. By embracing identity and its prickly, uncomfortable
contours, Americans will become more likely to grow as one.
STACEY Y. ABRAMS served as
Minority Leader of the Georgia House of Representatives from 2011 to 2017 and
was the Democratic Party’s nominee in Georgia’s 2018 gubernatorial election.
Identity Politics Can Lead to Progress
John Sides, Michael Tesler,
and Lynn Vavreck
Francis Fukuyama argues that
“identity politics has become a master concept that explains much of what is
going on in global affairs.” He attributes a variety of political developments
in the United States and abroad—especially the emergence of populist nationalism—to
identity politics. In Fukuyama’s telling, the rise of identity politics
constitutes a fall from grace. For him, most of “twentieth-century politics was
defined by economic issues.” But in the 1960s, he writes, the civil rights,
feminist, and other social movements embraced identity politics. Later, he
claims, forces on the political right followed suit, adopting “language and
framing from the left.” Fukuyama warns that if democratic societies continue
“fracturing into segments based on ever-narrower identities,” the result will
be “state breakdown and, ultimately, failure.”
Identity is indeed a “master
concept” for understanding American politics. But identity politics has a much
longer history than Fukuyama describes. And in the United States, identity
politics hasn’t led to the breakdown of democracy; rather, it has helped
democracy thrive.
ORIGIN STORY
In Fukuyama’s telling,
identity politics first emerged in the second half of the twentieth century. In
fact, Americans have been engaged in identity politics since the founding of
the republic. If the fight for civil rights for African Americans was fueled by
identity politics, then so was the fight to establish and ensure white supremacy via slavery and Jim Crow. In other words, identity politics
isn’t behind only the efforts of marginalized groups to seek redress: it also
drives the efforts of dominant groups to marginalize others.
Fukuyama believes identity
politics went too far when groups such as African Americans began to “assert a
separate identity” and “demand respect for [their members] as different from
the mainstream society.” Leaving aside whether that statement correctly characterizes
the goal of such groups, it is important to acknowledge that identity politics
also defined who was and who was not part of “mainstream society” in the first
place.
If the fight for civil rights
for African Americans was fueled by identity politics, then so was the fight to
establish and ensure white supremacy via slavery and Jim Crow.
In Fukuyama’s telling, U.S.
politics were healthier when Americans—especially those on the left—organized
around economic concerns that transcended ethnic categories. “In past eras,” he
writes, “progressives
appealed to a shared experience of exploitation and resentment of rich
capitalists.” But there is no period in U.S. history when economics were so
cleanly divorced from identity. For example, as the political scientist Ira Katznelson
has documented, the key social welfare programs of the New Deal era were
predicated on racial discrimination: U.S. President Franklin Roosevelt relied
on the support of white segregationists, which he won by allowing southern
states to prevent blacks from enjoying the New Deal’s benefits. Identity, and
especially racial and ethnic identity, has always been intrinsic to fights over
economic opportunity and equality.
This is not to say that
today’s identity politics is the same as its historical forebears. What makes
it different is how tightly Americans’ views about racial, ethic, and religious
identities are now bound up with another salient American identity: partisan
affiliation. Well before 2016, Democratic and Republican voters had begun to
diverge in their views of immigration
and racial equality. Democrats became more supportive of immigration and more
willing to attribute racial inequality to discrimination. Republicans became
less supportive of immigration and more willing to attribute racial inequality
to a lack of effort on the part of African Americans. This divergence sharpened
during Barack Obama’s candidacy and presidency, as whites’ racial attitudes
became more closely tied to their partisan identities.
This trend might have
accelerated even faster than it did had major political leaders tried to
exploit it. But Obama actually talked about race less than other recent
Democratic presidents and frequently used rhetoric that sought to unify
Americans of different racial backgrounds. Meanwhile, Obama’s Republican opponents
in the presidential elections of 2008 and 2012, John McCain and Mitt Romney,
chose not to stoke racialized fears of Obama.
Donald Trump was different.
His provocative statements about race, immigration, and Islam helped define the
2016 election. Partly as a result, Americans’ views on such issues became
stronger predictors of how they voted. For example, compared with in earlier
elections, it was easier to determine how people voted in 2016 based on whether
they wanted a pathway to citizenship for undocumented immigrants or believed
that racial inequality was just a matter of minorities “not trying hard
enough.” Meanwhile, economic issues achieved more political potency when
refracted through race. As far back as the 2016 Republican primary, whether
voters supported Trump depended less on whether they were worried about losing
their own jobs than it did on whether they were worried about whites losing
jobs to ethnic minorities.
WHOSE CHOICE?
Since the election, this
alignment of partisanship and attitudes about race and immigration has grown
even stronger, and it has an important implication for Fukuyama’s argument.
Fukuyama’s favored political agenda closely resembles that of Democratic voters
and the Democratic Party. He supports remedies for police violence against
minorities and the sexual harassment of women, endorses birthright citizenship,
and wants an American identity based on ideals rather than on “blood and soil”
nationalism.
The most forceful opposition
to such ideas has come from the Trump administration and its Republican allies
and supporters. Yet Fukuyama does not put the onus on Republicans to reject
Trump. In his view, the “major choice” belongs to the Democratic Party, which
must decide whether to double down on “the mobilization of . . . identity
groups” or “try to win back some of the white working-class voters . . . who
have defected” to the GOP. But if Fukuyama wants federal action on his policy
agenda in an era of divided government and narrow congressional majorities, the
real onus is on Republicans to support his ideas. And if he wants an American
identity based on shared values and open to all citizens—even those who hail
from what Trump reportedly called “shithole countries”—then he will need at
least some Republicans to stand up to Trump.
Fukuyama may be against
identity politics, but identity politics is also critical to the success of the
agenda that he supports. History has shown that progress toward equality
doesn’t come about because of happenstance, a sudden change of heart on Capitol
Hill, or the magnanimity of dominant groups. Instead, progress comes when
marginalized groups organize around their shared identities. Their fight is
often unpopular. In one 1964 survey, conducted a few months after the passage
of the Civil Rights Act, of those polled, 84 percent of southerners and 64
percent of Americans living outside the South said that civil rights leaders
were pushing too fast. But pushing was their only recourse, and pushing helped
change the country’s laws and attitudes.
Fukuyama wants a unifying
American identity, what he calls a “creedal national identity.” But the country
is already fairly close to having one. According to the December 2016 Views of
the Electorate Research, or VOTER, Survey, 93 percent of Americans think that
respecting U.S. political institutions and laws is somewhat or very important
to “being American.” Far fewer believe that it’s important to be born in the
United States (55 percent) or to have European heritage (20 percent). Moreover,
most Americans actually place identity politics at the center of the American
creed: the vast majority (88 percent) think that accepting people of diverse
racial and religious backgrounds is important to being American.
There is no necessary tension
between identity politics and the American creed. The question is whether
identity politics will help Americans live up to that creed. Historically, it
has.
JOHN SIDES, MICHAEL TESLER,
AND LYNN VAVRECK are political scientists and the authors of Identity Crisis: The 2016 Presidential
Campaign and the Battle for the Meaning of America.
A Creedal Identity Is Not Enough
Jennifer A. Richeson
Francis Fukuyama argues that
identity politics is eroding national unity in the United States and Europe,
undermining the kind of civil discourse essential to the maintenance of liberal
democracy. He also claims that “perhaps the worst thing about identity politics
as currently practiced by the left is that it has stimulated the rise of
identity politics on the right.” This is highly misleading. Identity politics
was part of the American political discourse long before liberals and leftists
began to practice it in the 1960s and 1970s. Think of the anti-immigrant
Know-Nothing Party in the 1850s and the white-supremacist Ku Klux Klan during the
first half of the twentieth century. What were such groups if not early
practitioners of a brand of white identity politics?
But other parts of Fukuyama’s
argument are more persuasive, and he is right to focus on the role that
identity plays in the health of American democracy. Fukuyama makes one
particularly useful point in the closing passages of his article:
People will never stop
thinking about themselves and their societies in identity terms. But people’s
identities are neither fixed nor necessarily given by birth. Identity can be
used to divide, but it can also be used to unify. That, in the end, will be the
remedy for the populist politics of the present.
Identity politics was part of
the American political discourse long before liberals and leftists began to
practice it in the 1960s and 1970s.
What Fukuyama gets right here
is the fact that human beings have a fundamental need to belong—a need that
their collective identities, be they racial, ethnic, religious, regional, or
national, often satisfy. Such affiliations, which psychologists call “social
identities,” serve multiple psychological functions. These include, for
example, the need for a sense of safety, which social identities satisfy by
reducing uncertainty and providing norms that help people navigate everyday
life. Some social identities also offer rituals and customs to aid with loss,
mourning, and other significant challenges that occur during the course of
one’s life. At times, identities provide a sense of purpose and meaning and a
basis for esteem and regard that is larger than people’s individual selves. As
Fukuyama suggests, identities efficiently satisfy the human need for respect
and dignity.
What Fukuyama gets wrong,
however, is the idea that a single unifying identity—a “creedal” American
identity—could alone satisfy this suite of psychological needs and thereby
allow citizens to abandon the smaller social identities that people invest in
and clearly value. Broad identities such as the one Fukuyama promotes are
useful and unifying at times, but they rarely meet the human need for
individuation. That is why people look to narrower bases for identification.
Moreover, broad social identities such as national affiliations—even when
ostensibly based on principles that are hypothetically accessible to all—often
rely on the terms and norms of the dominant majority and thus end up
undermining the identity needs of minority groups.
Furthermore, people’s
existing social identities are important to them, and attempts to dissolve them
would likely be met with severe resistance. The potential loss of a group’s
identity, real or imagined, is psychologically threatening. A powerful urge
compels people to defend their groups at all costs in the face of such threats.
As Fukuyama himself notes, a sense of loss due to the changing racial and
ethnic composition of the United States is partly to blame for the rise of
right-wing identity politics. Hence, it is important not only to cultivate a
common American identity, as Fukuyama argues, but also to promote the idea of
the United States as inclusive of multiple racial, ethnic, religious, and other
types of identities. Indeed, Americans must create that society.
WHY DON’T WE HAVE BOTH?
Perhaps the main weakness of
Fukuyama’s argument is the implication that Americans face a binary choice when
it comes to political identity: either they can embrace a broad creedal
identity or they can cling to narrow identities based on race, ethnicity,
gender, or ideology. There is no reason to think that is true. Political leaders
can address the sense of psychological vulnerability triggered by shifting
demographics and social change and also respect rightful claims for inclusion
and fair treatment on the part of members of marginalized groups. Americans can
acknowledge and, when appropriate, celebrate the particular identities,
cultures, and histories of distinct social groups and also pursue a unifying
national creed.
There is even some evidence
to suggest that the more identities people maintain—and the more complex and overlapping
those identities are—the less conflict they will have with people who maintain
different sets of identities. Greater identity complexity may serve as a buffer
against the feelings of humiliation and resentment that often fuel
ethnonationalist movements.
Identifying as American does
not require the relinquishing of other identities. In fact, it is possible to
leverage those identities to cultivate and deepen one’s Americanness. For
instance, researchers have found that when people highlight their shared
experiences, even when they belong to what appear to be opposing, if not
adversarial, social groups, they experience an increase in empathy and harmony.
Rather than dividing people, the act of reflecting on the marginalization of
one’s own social group—be it current or historical—can encourage societal
cohesion.
Identifying as American does
not require the relinquishing of other identities.
In the United States, an
honest accounting and acknowledgment of what it has meant to be American could
reveal Americans’ shared vulnerability and their common capacity for
wrongdoing, as well as their resilience in the face of mistreatment. This
sentiment is echoed by the lawyer and civil rights activist Bryan Stevenson,
who has argued for the need to engage honestly with the history of racial
injustice in the United States. “We can create communities in this country
where people are less burdened by our history of racial inequality,” Stevenson
told an interviewer last year. “The more we understand the depth of that
suffering, the more we understand the power of people to cope and overcome and
survive.”
That sounds like a unifying
national creed that would allow Americans to embrace their own identities,
encourage them to respect the identities embraced by others, and affirm shared
principles of equality and justice. Fukuyama appears to believe that this more
complex form of national identification is not possible. I think it is. It may
even be the only path toward a diverse nation that lives up to its democratic principles.
JENNIFER A. RICHESON is
Philip R. Allen Professor of Psychology at Yale University.
FUKUYAMA REPLIES
I appreciate these
thoughtful comments on my article. But all three responses, which contain a
number of common themes, fundamentally miscast my thinking about identity
politics. One reason for this might be that the article focuses more on the
kind of identity politics characteristic of the contemporary progressive left,
whereas the book from which the article was adapted, Identity, focuses
more on my central concern: the recent rise of right-wing nationalist populism.
This development threatens liberal democracy because populist leaders seek to
use the legitimacy they gain from democratic elections to undermine liberal
institutions such as courts, the media, and impartial bureauc-racies. This has
been happening in Hungary, Poland, and, above all, the United States.
Populists’ distrust of “globalism” also leads them to weaken the international
institutions necessary to manage the liberal world order.
I concur with the commonplace
judgment that the rise of populism has been triggered by globalization
and the consequent massive increase in inequality in many rich countries. But
if the fundamental cause were merely economic, one would have expected to see
left-wing populism everywhere; instead, since the 2008 financial crisis,
parties on the left have been in decline, while the most energized new
movements have been anti-immigrant groups, such as the far-right party
Alternative for Germany and the populist coalition now governing Italy. In the
2016 U.S. presidential election, enough white working-class voters abandoned
the Democratic Party to put Donald Trump over the top, capping a 40-year trend
of shifting party loyalties. This means that there is something going on in the
cultural realm that needs explaining, and that something is concern over
identity.
BALANCING IDENTITY
The concept of “identity,” as
I use the term, builds on a universal aspect of the human psyche that Plato
labeled thymos, the demand for respect for one’s inner dignity. But
there is a specifically modern expression of thymos that emerged after
the Protestant Reformation and that values the inner self more highly than
society’s laws, norms, and customs and insists that society change its own
norms to give recognition to that inner self. The first major expression of
modern identity politics was nineteenth-century European nationalism, when
cultural groups began to demand recognition in the form of statehood. I believe
that much of modern Islamism is similarly driven by identity confusion among
Muslims in modernizing societies who feel neither Western nor traditional and
see a particular form of politicized religion as a source of community and
identity.
But is not correct to say, as
John Sides, Michael Tesler, Lynn Vavreck, and Jennifer Richeson do, that
identity politics as I define it drove white-supremacist and anti-immigrant
movements in the nineteenth-century United States. Racism and xenophobia have
always existed. But a generation or two ago, white Americans did not typically
think of themselves as a victimized minority mistreated by elites who were
indifferent to their problems. Today, many do, because contemporary racists
have borrowed their framing of identity from groups on the left, in ways that resonate
with people who are not necessarily racist.
Another major
misunderstanding of my argument has to do with my view of contemporary identity
movements such as Black Lives Matter and #MeToo. Of course they are rooted
in real social injustices such as police violence and sexual harassment; they
legitimately call for concrete policy remedies and a broad shift in cultural
norms. But people can walk and chew gum at the same time. Even as Americans
seek to right injustices suffered by specific social groups, they need to
balance their small-group identities with a more integrative identity needed to
create a cohesive national democratic community. I am not arguing, contrary to
Richeson, that this will be an adequate substitute for narrower identities;
rather, it will be a complement to them.
Liberal democracy cannot
exist without a national identity that defines what citizens hold in common
with one another. Given the de facto multiculturalism of contemporary
democracies, that identity needs to be civic or creedal. That is, it needs to
be based on liberal political ideas that are accessible to people of different
cultural backgrounds rather than on fixed characteristics such as race,
ethnicity, or religion. I thought that the United States had arrived at such a
creedal identity in the wake of the civil rights movement, but that
accomplishment is now being threatened by right-wing identitarians, led by
Trump, who would like to drag Americans backward to identities based on
ethnicity and religion.
WINNING VS. GOVERNING
Stacey Abrams criticizes my desire
to return to class as the defining target of progressive politics, since class
and race overlap strongly in the United States. But it is absurd to see white
Americans as a uniformly privileged category, as she seems to do. A significant
part of the white working class has followed the black working class into
underclass status. Communities facing deindustrialization and job loss have
experienced increases in crime, family breakdown, and drug use; the Centers for
Disease Control and Prevention has estimated that 72,000 Americans died in 2017
of drug overdoses related to the opioid epidemic. So although part of the populist vote both in the United
States and in Europe is driven by racism and xenophobia, part of it is driven
by legitimate complaints that elites—the mainstream political parties, the
media, cultural institutions, and major corporations—have failed to recognize
these voters’ plight and have stood by as this decline has occurred.
Abrams knows much better than
I do what is required to win an election in the contemporary United States, and
I’m sorry that she did not succeed in her bid for governor of Georgia. But I’m
not sure that a successful electoral strategy would necessarily translate into
a sustainable governing strategy. The country’s single greatest weakness today
is the intense polarization that has infected its political system, a weakness
that has been exploited by authoritarian rivals such as China
and Russia.
In practical terms, overcoming polarization means devising a posture that will
win back at least part of the white working-class vote that has shifted from
the left to the right. Peeling away populist voters not driven by simple racism
means taking seriously some of their concerns over cultural change and national
identity. I agree that the burden is on Republican politicians to stop
defending Trump, but they will do so only when they realize that their own
voters are turning against him.
The contemporary Middle East, like the Balkans before it, is an extreme example of
out-of-control identity politics and what ultimately happens to countries that
do not invest in integrative national identities. The United States is
fortunately far from that point of state breakdown. But what is happening in
the country is part of a larger global shift from a politics based on economic
ideas to a politics based on identity. In the 2018 midterm elections, Trump was
reportedly advised by Paul Ryan, the Republican Speaker of the House, to
campaign on the 2017 tax cut and economic growth; Trump chose instead to go the
identity route by railing against migrant caravans and birthright citizenship. This is identity politics on
steroids.
This shift, echoed in other
countries, is not compatible with modern liberal democracy. The latter is
rooted in the rights of individuals, and not the rights of groups or fixed
communities. And unless the United States counters this trend domestically, it
will continue to set a bad example for the rest of the world.